.

Wednesday, February 27, 2019

Renaissance humanism

I naively expect that none of this would be controversial, and I was quite undisposed(p) for the hostility it fire among approximately legates to the congress, chiefly from Yankee europium, who represented what I came to perceive as the Lutheran Establishwork forcet. This group was concerned to insist on the total originality of Luther and the uniquely Ger patch Origins of the Recourseation. The paper would, I echo, be more than everydayly pass judgment today . It was first published in Luther and the Dawn of the Modern period Papers for the Fourth International Congress for Luther Research, De.H. A. Barman, Studies in the History of Christian Thought, Volvo. 8 (Elided E. J. Brills, 1974), up. 127-149. It is reprinted here by permission of the publisher . Since the peculiar in lineixture of righteousness and presumption in the title of my paper provide except bring forth escaped the nonice of this distinguished audience, I feel some need to explain at the outset th at it represents an assignment on the berth of those who planned our meeting.The logical implication of the difficultys to which it points is suggested by the great historians who harbor grapp guide with it in the past, albeit (a point that should constitute some thing of a warning) with somewhat contrary go outs, among them Michelle, Diluted, and Throttles. l Its applicative importance lies in the need of some of us to place our more limited inclusions in some broader historical framework we must hence reconsider, from ? 226 ? time to time, the consanguinity between renascence and Re actation.In hatred of this, the worst has recently cope withd precise opinionated attention, and many of us are still likely to rely, when we arise it, on unexamined and obsolete stereotypes. Obviously I can non hope to remedy this assert of affairs in a brief paper. Yet the progress of conversion studies in recent decades invites a reassessment of this classic problem, and I bear these remarks as an essay intended to stimulate further concussion. What has chiefly suppress larger generalization has been the extension and refinement of our k in a flashledge, and with it a growth two in limitedization and in humility.Thus we are increasingly reluctant to furtheste broad pronouncements to the highest degree either the rebirth or the Reformation, much slight about two(prenominal) at once. For as scholars we are divided non and between renascence and Reformation, or between Italy and Northern Europe tear down within these categories most of us are specialists who would claim competency barely in a specific perspective of spiritual rebirth Florence or Venice, in one phase or some other of Renaissance pieceism, in Machiavelli or Erasmus, in later scholasticism or the archives of righteousness, in Luther or Calvin or the sects.nether these conditions few students of the Renaissance have cared to look as far as the Reformation and although Reform ation scholars have been somewhat bolder, they have rarely pursued the question of Renaissance antecedents farther than northern benevolentism. military manitarianism is, therefore, the one theatre of operations that has recently encouraged forays into the problem of this paper exclusively although Barren, Devour, Spits, Libeling, and especi bothy Charles Trinkets, among others, have made valuable intrusions to discussion,2 the problem is still with us, primarily, I think, because we have non full phase of the moony made up our minds about the consequence of Renaissance pityingism.A result of this difficulty has been a tendency to focus special attention on Erasmus as a touchstone for the Renaissance, a post for which?for earths that result emerge later in this paper?I think he is not exclusively suited. It is, however, one footmark of the complexity of our subject that we cannot approach the question of the blood between Renaissance and Reformation without someways f irst coming to terms with the implications of pieceism. I should like to do so, however, sidelong benignanta than at a time.It faces to me that although clementism, which assumed a shape of forms as it passed by means of with(predicate) incidental stages and was influenced by differing local conditions, was not identical with the more expectant tendencies of Renaissance destination, it was nevertheless(prenominal) oft likely to give them notable expression, and for footings that were not accidental besides broadcastly related to the rhetorical tradition whatever their ?227 ? differences in other respects, most recent interpretations of Renaissance humanism have at least identified it with a revival of rhetoric. What has been less gener tout ensembley recognize is the deeper significance of this revival. The major reason is, I think, that in our time the term rhetoric has become generally pejorative we are inclined to friction match it with the adjective mere. t hat for the Renaissance there was nothing shallow about rhetoric. Based on a set of profound assumptions about the nature, competence, and tidy sum of man, rhetoric gave expression to the deepest tendencies of Renaissance nicety, tendencies by no meaner confined to men clearly identifiable as humanists, nor always fully expressed by men who have generally been considered humanists.I shall try in this paper to let out these tendencies, which seem to me to have exerted intolerable pressures on fundamental elements in the chivalric intellect of Christianity. And I impart suggest that similar tendencies underlay the mentation of the great Protestant Reformers. Thus the significance of Protestantism in the development of European polish lies in the fact that it accepted the religious consequences of these Renaissance tendencies and was prepared to apply them to the understanding of the Gospel.From this standpoint the Reformation was the theological fulfillment of the Renaissance . I Fundamental to the cultural movements of the Renaissance was a gradual accumulation of contour and governmental potpourris an economy increasingly dependent on commerce rather than agriculture a political structure composed of assertive exceptional powers and a society dominated by educated laymen who were increasingly rebellious under clerical direction and increasingly aggressive in press their have got claims to dignity and self-determination.A commercial economy and the more and more openly uncoordinated conduct of politics supplied the social base for a in the altogether-fangled vision of mans place in the earth, and of the valet itself. Social figure grow in the land had perhaps encouraged a superstar of broad, essential regularities last-ditchly responsive to cosmic forces and inhibiting to a reason of the significance of modify but the vivification of a merchant community and the ambitious trading operations of independent rulers made all experienc eledge contingent on the interaction between unpredictable forces and the working ingenuity and energies of men.Under these conditions the possibility of cosmic sight seemed remote, but in any case of little relevance to human affairs and the obvious rule of change in the empirical world encouraged efforts at its comprehension and eventually ? 228 ? stimulated the awareness of history, that curiously Hebraic and Christian?as opposed to classic or Hellenic?contribution to the Western consciousness.Meanwhile rude(a) political realities and the claims of laymen undermined the hierarchical universes that had defined the essential structure of the old unified order of the cosmos, within which the affairs of this world had been assigned their proper place. 4 It will also be useful to obtain at this point that these developments were by no meaner confined to Italy I will touch briefly at a later point on the implications of this fact for the Renaissance problem.It is not altogeth er wrong to emphasize the collateral consequences of these developments which, by freeing human activity from any connection with ultimate patterns of order, liberated an exuberance that found expression in the various dimensions of Renaissance creativity. Bureaucrats insight that the familiarity of politics converted the prince into an artist of sorts may posit modification yet the new situation made all human arrangements potentially creative in a sense hardly workable so long as the basic principles of every activity were deduced from universal principles.The notion of the state as a work of art points to the general process of colonization and reminds us that the culture of the Renaissance extended far beyond its brilliant art and literature, and was perhaps even more of import in its implications than in its accomplishments. It had, however, another and darker side. It rest on the destruction of the sense of a definable relationship between man and ultimate realities. It part his connection with haughty principles of order, not so much by denying their being as by rejecting their accessibility to the human understanding.It deprived him of a traditional conception of himself as a being with distinct and organized faculties attuned to the similarly organized structure of an unchanging, and in this sense dependable, universe. Above all, therefore, it left him both alone in a mysterious world of unpredictable and often hostile forces, and at the corresponding time personally responsible in the most radical sense for his own ultimate destiny. For he was now left without reliable principles and? because the directive claims of the church also depended heavily on the old conceptions?reliable agencies of guidance.These darker aspects of Renaissance culture eventually squired, therefore, a reformulation of Christian belief, and we shall now examine them a bit more closely. Renaissance notion has sometimes been represented as a reassertion of old-fashio ned freethinking against the supernaturalism of the Middle Ages. The formulation is, of course, both inaccurate and misleading. In the ordinal cytosine some ideaual leaders had been notably hospitable to Greek philosophy, and had tried to coordinate it with revelation. moreover ? 229 ? it was precisely the possibility of such coordination that Renaissance culture?insofar as it differed from what had preceded it?characteristically denied in this sense Renaissance ruling was less wiseistic (if not necessarily less rational) than that of the Middle Ages. In fact it was inclined to distinguish between realms, between ultimate loyaltys altogether inaccessible to mans intellect, and the knowledge man needed to get along in this world, which turned out to be sufficient for his purposes.Thus the Renaissance attack on scholasticism had a larger implication as well as a specific target it implied, and occasionally led to, the rejection of all systematic philosophy. From Patriarch, thro ugh Salutation and Villa, to Machiavelli, Pompano, ND the Venetians of the later Renaissance, the leaders of Renaissance sentiment rejected any effort to ground human reflection or action on metaphysics and at the same time they insisted on the autonomy of the various dimensions of human concern and the relativity of truth to the practical requirements of the human condition.In this sense, although truth was robbed of some grandeur, it was also made more human and if Aristotle was less and less respected as a vehicle of eternal wisdom, he could be all the more admired as a man. 5 Under such conditions philosophy could evidently contribute nothing to theology indeed, its virtual(prenominal) effects were likely to be adverse since it encouraged malice and pride. related to the attack on metaphysical shot was an attack on pecking order, which rested ultimately on metaphysically based conceptions of the internal structure of all reality.The repudiation of hierarchy was most profoundl y expressed in Nicholas of Cusss conception of the infinite, which made every entity equally distant from?and thus equally tight to? god6 a similar impulse perhaps lurks behind Villas rejection of Pseudo-Dionysus. 7 But partly because the formulations of Susan smacked too such of metaphysics, partly because the problem of hierarchy was peculiarly related to social change, the attack on hierarchy was likely to receive more overtly social expression.It took a general form in the effort to substitute a dynamic conception of nobility through virtue for the static nobility of birth,8 a specific form in the impulse (often expressed in legislation and the practical policies of states)9 to consider the clergy in no way superior to other men but, on the contrary, as equal in the obligations of citizenship (if generally less competent in practical affairs), at least as alienable to sin, and in as larger-than- look a need for salvation as other men, whom it was their obligation to look rath er than to command.This suggested at least that social order was unrelated to cosmic order, but it also raised the possibility that order per SE was of a kind quite different from what had been supposed. For the age of the Renaissance was by no meaner oblivious to the ? 230 ? need for order, which indeed historical disasters had converted into the most urgent of problems. But its very urgency intensified the necessity of regarding order as a practical rather than a metaphysical issue. Bitter experience seemed to demonstrate that order had to be brought down to earth, where it could be defined in limited and manageable ways.And, as the occasional intrusions of the clergy into politics appeared periodically to demonstrate, the set out to apply ultimate principles to concrete problems was likely merely to interfere with their practical solution. This was a central point not only for Machiavelli and his polities successors it also molded the numerous constitutional experiments of the Renaissance, with their repudiation of hierarchically defined lines of authority in favor of order through a balance of interests and their compendium to quick local require and the right of local self- determination.The beaver arrangements, in these terms, were not those that most accurately reflected some absolute pattern but those that best served the specific and limited human purposes for which they were instituted. But although a sense of the confinement of the human intellect was basic to the thought of the Renaissance, this negation had a positive corollary in a new conception of the human personality which also seemed to equal better to the experience supplied by a new social environment.Men whose lives consisted in the broad range of experiences, ontogenesis, and human relationships that characterized existence in the bustling and entangled modern world could no longer find plausible an get up conception of man as a hierarchy of faculties properly subject to reaso n instead the personality presented itself as a complex and forked unity in which the will, primarily responsive to the passions, occupied a mental attitude at the con midpoint.One result of this conception was to undermine the contemplative paragon if mans reason was weak but his will strong, he could only realize himself in this world through action, indeed he was meant for a heart of action. some other was to reduce suspicion of the body in the absence of the old mental hierarchy, the body could no longer be held merely base and contemptible. accomplishment required its use, and the new integrity of the personality reduced the possibility of attributing the human propensity to evil primarily to the physical or sensual aspect of mans nature.Human passions now also acquired a positive value, as the source of action. 10 This new anthropology, articulated by Patriarch, Salutation, and Villa, required a reconsideration of the problem of immortality and led eventually to the ar dent discussions of the soul in which Pompano figured. It also pointed to the political and historical conceptions of Machiavelli and Caricaturing, who emphasized the primacy of will and passion, as well as to the psychological interests of a host of Renaissance writers. 11 ? 231 ? In addition man was defined as a social being if he lost one kind of company in a larger reality, namely his plume ready as a member of the human species in the cosmic hierarchy of being, he, obtained another with, perhaps, more tangible satisfactions his membership as a concrete exclusive in the particular human community in which he lived, now an essential rather than an accidental condition of is existence. Thus the set of human community now achieved full intelligence.Human virtue was defined not as an abstraction but as a function of relationship with other men mans active nature was understood to achieve full expression only in a life of social responsibility, and indeed his happiness was see n as dependent on human community. Furthermore, since effective company in society required some wealth, the conception struck another blow at medieval asceticism. On the other hand the demands of life in society also stimulated a vision of human existence very different from that implicit in the contemplative ideal.For life in society was patently marked by a remainder of opposing interests that could rarely (if men were honest) be identified with absolute skillful or evil and to incessant struggle with other men was added, in social existence, the temptations that inevitably beset anyone who chooses to engage with rather than to withdraw from the world. The life clutch to men in this world was thus not love-in-idleness (however desperately one might long for it) 12 but a unending and moralisticly ambiguous warfare, with the outcome ever in doubt. By the same token earthly life had also to be seen as dynamic, as subject to change in all its aspects.Human communities could be seen to rise, flourish, and decay and the philological investigations of Renaissance humanists supplemented common experience by revealing the general outlines of ancient civilization and thus demonstrating how much had changed during the intervening centuries. 13 They also wrote histories that communicated not only this perspective on the past, with its implication that human culture is not an absolute but relative to its times, but in addition other aspects of the Renaissance vision of life the active and social nature of man, the values of community, the incapableness of conflict and change.This vision found its fullest expression in the rhetorical culture of the Renaissance. Humanist oratory was based on the conception of man as a social being motivated by a will whose energies stemmed from the passions. This conception led in turn to a typical concern with communication as the essential bond of life in society, as well as to a new human ideal of the well-rounded, eloquent, an d thus socially effective man of affairs.The purpose of communication, in this view, could not be the transmission of an absolute wisdom, which the human mind was incompetent to reach, but the attainment of concrete and practical ends. ? 232 ? Such communication had above all to be persuasive it had to affect the will by swaying the passions, rather than merely to convince the mind in short it needed to penetrate to the center of the personality in order to achieve results in visible acts. And the significance of the need for persuasion should also be remarked.It implied a life in society that could not be controlled by authority and coercion through a hierarchical chain of command but depended instead on the inward assent of individuals. It was therefore no accident that the rhetorical culture of Italian humanism achieved its fullest development in republics. In addition the needs of broad communication pointed eventually to the development and use of vernacular languages, a more i mportant concern of Renaissance humanism than has sometimes been recognized. 14 II It should be immediately apparent that this set of attitudes imposed great strains on traditional Catholicism. 1 5 It undermined the effort to base earthly existence on abstract principles identified with divine wisdom, and to relate the visible and changing world of public experience to the invisible and immutable realm of the spirit. Both the comforts in this relationship and its implications for the guidance and intro of lower things by higher were gravely threatened.From a Renaissance perspective the arguments by which it was supported seemed at best frivolous, at worst a specious rationalization of claims to power in this world on behalf of a group of men whose attention should be directed exclusively to the next. And behind such suspicions we may also get it on the perception of man as primarily a creature of will and passion. In this light intellectual claims were likely to be construed as m asks for motives that could not bear inspection dogma itself might be no more than an instrument of tyranny.In addition, since a contemplative repose now seemed inappropriate to the demonstrable nature of man, as well as a breach of responsibility for the welfare of others, the ideal form of the Christian life required redefinition. Finally, the problem of salvation was transformed. Alone in an ultimately unintelligible universe, and with the more unfathomed conception of sin and the problems of its control opened up by the new anthropology, man could no longer count on the mediation either of reason or of other men in closer affaire with the divine than himself.His salvation depended on an immediate and personal relation with God. here(predicate) it is necessary to pause for a more searching look at one of the key terms of our title Renaissance . The conceptions I have so far reviewed ? 233 ? have been based largely on developments in Italy, and this would suggest a vision of t he Renaissance, or of Renaissance culture, as initially and perhaps primarily an Italian affair.But this audience is well aware that the tendencies I have described were also present in a variety of movements outside Italy, if in somewhat different forms. It is obvious, for example, that later medieval piety exhibited similar impulses ND that, in spite of the antipathy of humanists to scholastic speculation (though here we need to be more precise about what was in reality under attack), the later schoolmate played a major if largely independent part in bringing underlying assumptions to the surface and in attempting to accommodate theology to them. 16 Perhaps, therefore, the time has come to expand, as well as to make more specific, our conception of what was central to the age of the Renaissance, and also to waive the traditional contrast between Italy and the North, which seems to me to eve been in some measure the result of a failure to get beneath surface differences.If I have concentrated on Italian thought in this sketch, I have done so partly to bring out the fundamental frequency unity of European spiritual development, partly because the affinities between Protestantism and later scholasticism have been more regularly a concern of Reformation experience than the parallels with the Renaissance in Italy. What is nevertheless increasingly clear is that the process of redefining Christianity to bring it into correspondence with the new assumptions about man and the world as gradual, and that it was pickings place simultaneously throughout Europe.Largely because of the recent profound book of Charles Trinkets, it is inessential to review in detail the process by which the pressures for religious change implicit in the assumptions of Renaissance culture operated among the humanists of Italy. They are already transparent in Patriarch, and they seem to have reached a climax in Lorenz Villa. In a general sense they may be attributed to the special solit ude and despair of men who could no longer regard religious truth as a body of knowledge of the name order as other knowledge that was communicable through similar kinds of intelligible discourse.Nor could the institutional fiddles encouraged by ecclesiastical authority as an alternative to rational theology provide a satisfactory solution to the problem. Not only did the idea of implicit faith clash with the growing sense of individual spiritual dignity among pious laymen in addition, discredited by its impotence, its worldliness, the presumed irrelevance of its abstract theology, and a sacramental and disciplinary externalities increasingly inadequate to relieve the profanely intense guilt of the age, the church could no longer be regarded as a dependable guarantor of truth. ? 234 ? Thus, driven by a profound yearning for immediate contact with the eternal,17 the humanists of the early Italian Renaissance move perceptibly toward a simple religion of grace based on the Scripture s and apprehended by the individual through faith. Patriarch typically began with insights into his own inner conflicts and the discovery that these could only be resolved by throwing himself on Gods mercy in a faith that was at once the highest form of knowledge and at the same time different n kind from all other knowledge confusion on this point seemed to him the most dangerous error.Salutation, concerned as a sterner moralist to protect human freedom and responsibility within a religion of grace, wrestled with the problem of predestination. And with Villa excuse by faith received an even fuller exploration, the role of priest and sacrament in the economy of salvation was correspondingly reduced, and that of Scripture, the Word whose authenticity could be established by philology and which spoke directly to the individual, was enlarged. 18 match to the distinction between philosophy and faith was the demand or a sharper distinction between the church and the world the separati on of realms in one area seemed to lead naturally to separation in others. In its demands for a spiritual church, the new historicism of the Renaissance col agitateated with the insistence of the Italian states on freedom from clerical interference and with their grievances against Rome as a political force. 19 The study of the historical church revealed the spiritual costs of the confusion of realms. 20 At the very least, as men of the Renaissance with some political experience were in a position to know, the effective use of power in the world was always morally ambiguous21 and meanwhile the growing participation of popes and prelates in secular politics had been accompanied by an increasing heedlessness of the spiritual mission of the church. Thus, if reform required a return to the past, the reason was above all that the early church had been true to its spiritual characters. 22 barely a spiritual church, devoted to that which does not change, could stand above history and thu s resist decay.Villas attack on the Donation of Constantine was not an uncaring document23 it fleets a concern with the church, its earthly role and its spiritual mission, that runs through much of Renaissance historiography, from Muscat at the beginning of the fourteenth century to Machiavelli, Caricaturing, and Far Paolo Carpi. 24 The rediscovery of grace was closely related to the new vision of man philosophy, as Patriarch recognized, was incapable of converting man at the crucial center of his being. It is one thing to know, he declared, another to love one thing to understand, another to will. What was required was a shift not merely of the intellect but of the ? 235 ? hole personality, so that Christian conversion would find appropriate expression in a life of love and active responsibility for the welfare of others. And, as in the world, the essential meaner for such a transformation was not rational appeal to the intellect but rhetorical appeal to those deeper levels in ma n that alone could move the will. Thus Patriarch argued for the favourable position over rational philosophers of moral teachers who could sow the love of virtue in the very hearts of men. 25 For Villa rhetoric was thus the only branch of secular learning (except for philology) applicable to theology. 26 The implications of this position for the importance and character of preaching seem clear. A new conception of man was also reflected in a changed conception of God, in accordance, perhaps, not only with Renaissance emphasis on mans creation in Gods likeness and image but also with Callings recognition of the reciprocal relationship between mans understanding of himself and his knowledge of God. 27 Like man, God could no longer be perceived as a contemplative being, as Aristotle unmoved mover, operating in the universe not directly but through a research of intermediate powers. 28 Laymen active in the world required a God who was also active, who exercised a direct and vigilant co ntrol over all things, like that to which they aspired for themselves.God too had therefore to be perceived as primarily will, intellectually beyond mans scope yet revealing something of himself? all, at any rate, that man needed to know?in his actions, above all as recorded in dedicated Scripture. And from Patriarchs sense of the free, mysterious, and incalculable nature of God,29 Salutation went on to defend the human representations f God in the Bible as a form of communication appropriate to mens capacities. 30 Villa was, as one might expect, even clearer that the God of philosophy could not be the God of faith. 31 In spite of all this, it is nevertheless undeniable that the culture of the Italian Renaissance did not culminate in Protestantism, although even on this point our old sense of the immunity of Italy to the impulses of the Reformation is no longer altogether tenable. 32 Yet it remains true that the religious thought of Renaissance Italy remained no more than an in coherent bundle of monumental insights, and it was unable to rid itself of fundamental contradictions again, however, the contrast with Northern Europe seems hardly absolute.Above all it failed to complete its conviction of mans intellectual limitations, which pushed him only part of the way into the realm of grace, with full conviction of his moral impotence. level(p) here its vision of man suggests a deepening in the understanding of sin and the human obstacles to salvation and there is abundant evidence of a pessimistic estimate of the human condition in Patriarch, Salutation, Pogo, Villa, and later, in a different form, in Machiavelli andCaricaturing. Yet Renaissance emphasis on the central importance of the will frequently served chiefly to nourish the moralist that so deeply permeated later medieval piety,33 contributing both to the notion of Christianity as the pursuit of moral perfection and of the church as essentially a system of government 34 Renaissance humanism remaine d, in Lathers sense, Appealing.The consequence was, however, that Renaissance culture in Italy, like Scholastic theology in the north, helped to intensify, from both directions at once, the unbearable tension between he moral obligations and the moral capacities of the Christian that could at last find relief only in either a repudiation of Renaissance attitudes or the theology of the Reformation. But it could not resolve the problem itself, and we must ask why this was so. role of the explanation is connected with the fact that some among the figures we have cited were lacking in theological interests, while the rest were amateurs whose major activity lay elsewhere.The result was an inability to develop the full implications of their assumptions, which was supplemented by prejudice against intellectual labor too closely resembling the Scholasticism they despised. In addition, closely attached to particular societies in which, traditionally, no distinction was made between Christia nity and citizenship, they were unable to ach

No comments:

Post a Comment